Registration is open for the 2024 ASRM Scientific Congress & Expo

Menu
Close Close Icon
Ethics Committee teaser

Compassionate transfer: patient requests for embryo transfer for nonreproductive purposes

A patient request to transfer embryos into her body in a location or at a time when pregnancy is highly unlikely to occur is deemed a request for ‘‘compassionate transfer’’ and often reflects the patient’s deeply personal, strongly held preferences and values. It is ethically permissive for physicians to honor or decline such requests if they do so in a nondiscriminatory manner. (Fertil Steril® 2020;113:62–5. ©2019 by American Society for Reproductive Medicine.)

Download a PDF of this document

KEY POINTS:

  • A patient request to transfer potentially viable embryos into her body in a location or at a time when pregnancy is highly unlikely to occur, and when pregnancy is not the intended outcome, is deemed a request for ‘‘compassionate transfer.’’
  • Valid and reasoned arguments exist to support provider decisions to perform the compassionate transfer of embryos for nonreproductive purposes and to decline to assist in such transfers. Principles of reproductive liberty, physician autonomy, medical futility, nonmaleficence, and distributive justice are potentially invoked in decision-making in this area.
  • Programs should develop explicit written policies and procedures for handling requests for compassionate transfer of embryos, including requirements for written informed consent, and make these written policies available to all patients.


INTRODUCTION

Patient requests to transfer embryos when pregnancy is not desired may raise clinical and ethical dilemmas for providers and their patients. During in vitro fertilization (IVF), embryo transfer ordinarily is performed to produce pregnancy and childbirth. In rare but clinically and ethically significant instances, a patient requests transfer of existing cryopreserved embryos into her body with intent not to reproduce but rather to dispose of the embryo(s). These patients, for one or more deeply personal reasons, desire a method of disposition other than laboratory discard, donation for research or third-party reproduction, or continued cryopreservation. Instead, they seek thaw and transfer into their bodies in a location, manner, or time in which implantation and pregnancy are calculated not to occur. An embryo transfer for nonreproductive purposes is often called a ‘‘compassionate transfer’’ to reflect a provider’s benevolent empathy in facilitating a patient’s desired method of embryo disposition. The Committee adopts the term ‘‘compassionate transfer’’ herein to describe embryo transfer when pregnancy is not intended but also acknowledges it is not a term of exclusion; provider compassion toward patient choices is certainly not limited to requests for nonreproductive embryo transfer. This Opinion discusses the practice of compassionate transfer from the perspective of patients and providers. It further examines the clinical and ethical considerations for fertility clinics in providing or declining to provide these services upon patient request.


TRANSFER OF EMBRYOS WHEN PREGNANCY IS UNDESIRED

Current IVF technologies allow patients to cryopreserve embryos developed from a treatment cycle, thus deferring disposition of these frozen embryos until a later date. To facilitate this decision-making process, clinics and providers solicit written instructions from patients and, where applicable, their partners as to their preferences for disposition of frozen embryos under a range of potential circumstances in the future. While many patients initially elect embryo cryopreservation in hope of increasing their chance of pregnancy and live birth in the future, up to 40% of these cryopreserved embryos ultimately will not be used for reproduction and remain unused (1). A 2002 study of 340 clinics specializing in assisted reproductive technology (ART) found that a significant number of embryos remain in long-term storage, raising questions about how patients make decisions about embryo disposition and why they leave their embryos in storage. Clinics that offer cryopreservation typically request that patients express their desires regarding ultimate disposition of embryos not used for reproductive purposes. Patients are asked to indicate their preferences in a written form, generally setting out three (or possibly four) available options: 1) donate the unused embryos to research, 2) donate the embryos to another infertile patient, 3) allow the embryos to be discarded after thaw in the laboratory, or in some cases, 4) store the embryos indefinitely (2). In some instances, clinics may provide thawed embryos to patients for disposal so long as such practice is permitted by law.

Survey data and published legal disputes indicate that even when patients select an option for disposition at the time of treatment, they may change their mind at a later time (3). Given the potential of cryopreserved embryos to be successfully thawed and used for reproductive purposes well into the future, the opportunity for changes in the patient’s life course and reproductive desires abound. In some instances, disputes arise between the patient and her partner over the disposition of unused embryos. It is currently unknown, but possible, that an option for nonreproductive transfer could alleviate disputes concerning embryo disposition.

Patients' disposition decisions in general can be emotionally complex or distressing, ethically challenging, and lead some patients to postpone a decision for as long as possible. Some research indicates that indecision about embryo disposition can result in an estimated 20% of patients leaving their embryos in storage indefinitely (1; 4). Patients who do not discard or donate their embryos reveal that embryos continue to have significance to them, representing the potential to become a child, or their "virtual child," even when they have no desire to use the embryos for reproduction (5). For some, it may seem impossible to reconcile their view about the moral status of the embryos with any of the disposition options available to them. Research on patients' decisions about disposition has found that many patients would prefer disposition options not made available to them, such as being present for or involved in the disposal or holding a ceremony at the time of disposal or burial at a place and in a manner that state regulations governing the disposal of biological material may prohibit (2, 6). Despite some evidence that patients would select the option of compassionate transfer if made available for embryo discard, at least some research indicates that fewer than 5% of US clinics offer this option to patients (7).

Patient requests for compassionate embryo transfer in a manner that is highly unlikely to lead to pregnancy, and when pregnancy is not the intended outcome, may be attractive to some because the process is closely analogous to the natural in vivo failure of embryos to implant, an outcome potentially associated with every embryo-transfer procedure (7). Some variation on the practice of compassionate transfer may permit transfer to a place in the woman’s body where pregnancy will not likely occur, such as the vagina, or placement in the uterus at a time in the woman’s cycle when pregnancy is highly unlikely to result. Patient-advocacy organizations have supported compassionate transfer, as evidenced by the inclusion of this option for embryo disposition alongside those typically offered by ART clinics (8). One of the few studies to examine patient views about compassionate transfers found that about 20% would be interested in this alternative (9). Those patients who prefer this disposition, letting the embryos be absorbed in the body, see it as more respectful, personal, or natural than disposal in the laboratory. Moreover, compassionate transfer may be virtually the only acceptable option for patients in an estimated 16% of US IVF programs that for religious, ethical, or other reasons do not permit discard in the laboratory (2).

Until recently, data on the availability of compassionate transfer were scant, though one 2009 article indicated that fewer than 5% of all US fertility clinics offered this option to patients (7). In a 2018 survey of members of the Society for Reproductive Endocrinology and Infertility (SREI), more information became known about provider practices and attitudes toward compassionate transfer. The SREI survey revealed that nearly 45% of all responders who were aware of this option had offered the service to a patient (10). A greater percentage of those surveyed (78%) reported that they would offer compassionate transfer if there was patient demand, while 45% said they would offer the option if there was guidance from ASRM in place addressing the practice. The survey also revealed variation in practice as to the location of embryo transfer (endometrium, vagina, cervix), the timing of embryo transfer, the number of embryos transferred, and the fee structures in place when a transfer was performed. Three providers reported pregnancies from compassionate transfer, though none were ectopic (10).


ETHICAL CONSIDERATIONS

The arguments for honoring patient requests to transfer embryos when pregnancy is not desired dwell in the realm of reproductive liberty, patient autonomy, and provider beneficence. Reproductive liberty is a broad-based principle that protects against outside interference with patient control over reproductive decision-making, including decisions about the disposition of embryos (11). A liberty-based argument in favor of compassionate transfer focuses on the harms that result from infringement on this patient choice, whether those barriers are imposed by providers, the state, or other third parties. The principle of patient autonomy, a respected value in reproductive medicine, also arguably includes the right to control one’s embryos as a feature of patient self-determination. This Committee has previously acknowledged that some requests in assisted reproduction may be generated by a patient's deeply held private beliefs and values that are deserving of respect (12, 13). These beliefs and rationales are compatible with the exercise of reproductive liberty and patient autonomy.

The ethical principle of beneficence may also support a provider’s decision to honor patient requests for compassionate transfer. According to this principle as applied in the medical setting, providers have a duty to act for the patient’s welfare. The Committee has previously discussed that patients’ treatment goals can include purely psychological, rather than physiological, benefits from the requested medical intervention (14). Allowing patients to undergo embryo transfer not intended to result in pregnancy can enhance patients’ emotional, psychological, and social welfare; it thus may fulfill a physician’s duty of beneficence as it is understood in its psychosocial dimension.

The arguments for declining patient requests rely on principles of physician autonomy, nonmaleficence, medical futility, and distributive justice. Physicians are not obligated to meet every patient request, particularly when treatment is futile or highly unlikely to engender any medical benefit (14). Compassionate transfer provides no medical benefit to the patient, and in fact is specifically calculated to avert the benefit for which the embryos were originally created. Providers may also argue against honoring patient requests out of concern for potential harms or unnecessary risks to patient well-being, including the remote possibilities of pelvic infection, ectopic pregnancy, and uterine implantation, leading to miscarriage or an unintended pregnancy (7). Additional factors that have an effect on providers and argue against compassionate transfer include the view that these transfers are an inappropriate use of resources, including provider and staff time, and can cause facility inaccessibility for others. An additional argument that compassionate transfer need not be made available to patients is based on notions of efficiency. Since patients intend the ultimate outcome of compassionate transfer to be embryo discard, the additional resources required to achieve this result compared to the traditional means of discard in the laboratory cannot be ethically justified (15). This argument, however technically accurate, fails to account for any emotional or psychological benefit a patient might gain as a result of directing disposition in a manner of her choice.

Other arguments for declining to provide compassionate transfer highlight ethical misgivings about performing a procedure that has no medical benefit, while at the same time requiring additional patient financial outlay because the procedure is not eligible for insurance coverage. As the Committee has previously discussed (14), clinicians may ethically refuse to provide treatment when, in their professional judgment, they regard such treatments as futile with minimal or no chance of success. Additionally, ethical considerations involve the concept of distributive justice, provoked by the clinical reality that compassionate transfer is only available to female patients. Single males or same-sex male couples who secure embryos for reproduction have no opportunity to seek embryo demise in the same manner as female patients, that is within their body. The Committee believes that enlisting a woman for this purpose exceeds the ethical parameters governing collaborative reproduction, as no reproduction is intended and no benefit to her can result. While single males or same-sex male couples may seek compassionate transfer for reasons aligned with those expressed by female patients, the risk/benefit ratio in third-party embryo transfer for nonreproductive purposes positions it outside the scope of ethical justification.

finally, the Committee acknowledges that it can be psychologically, emotionally, and morally difficult for a patient to be in a position to activate a disposition decision for excess embryos. A compassionate transfer decision can lessen the sense of moral distress for some patients by allowing them to conclude that the ultimate outcome for their embryo— whether it implants or not—was made by nature, divine intervention, or a higher power, rather than the patient herself. While the belief that the ultimate outcome of the embryo was directed or decreed by some outside force may be a comfort to patients, it can be argued that this rationale is a form of self-deception or intentionally misconstruing the outcome of the transfer. Providers may object to colluding in patients’ self-deception, preferring to encourage patients to address and resolve psychological, emotional, and/or moral dilemmas regarding excess embryos.


CONSENT AND DISCLOSURE CONSIDERATIONS

Patient requests for compassionate transfer should be regarded the same as patient requests for embryo transfer for reproductive purposes as far as matters of consent are concerned. Generally speaking, informed consent for embryo transfer, including compassionate transfer, must be obtained from both the patient and her partner, and must address all reasonably foreseeable risks including the possibility of pregnancy. In addition, patients must be notified of the cost of such procedures. In the event a patient and her partner disagree over the disposition of embryos, a provider can look to any preconception or other agreements the parties entered into for guidance. In the absence of specific language governing compassionate transfer, or in the event of ambiguity or uncertainty, providers are strongly encouraged to seek counsel from a qualified legal expert. Under no circumstances should compassionate transfer be performed without the express written informed consent of the patient into whom the embryos are being transferred.

Providers may accommodate patient requests for compassionate transfer either by performing the embryo transfer or transferring the embryos to another provider or facility willing to perform the requested compassionate embryo transfer. Patients are always free to transfer their embryos to another center that is willing to accommodate their disposition preferences. In the case of either direct service or transfer to another facility, providers are obligated to fully inform the patient of the potential risks involved. Moreover, providers are obliged to comply with preexisting reporting requirements governing embryo transfer, including any specific requirements surrounding compassionate transfer of embryos. In addition, any embryo thaw or transfer should be well documented in the patient’s medical record. Clinics are strongly encouraged to develop and make available written policies to inform patients of their practices with regard to the disposition of embryos when pregnancy is not desired.


CONCLUSIONS

Patient decisions about embryo transfer and disposition in general are complex and, as is shown in the instances above, impact both providers and patients. Patient requests for embryo transfer in a place or at a time when pregnancy is highly unlikely to occur often reflect deeply held individual preferences and values and are entitled to respect. Principles of reproductive liberty and patient autonomy support these patient requests as a method of exercising control over a broad range of reproductive choices. It is ethically permissible for providers to honor such requests, so long as they engage in an adequate informed-consent process with the patient. However, providers are not obligated to provide such services. Physician autonomy, concerns about the provision of nonbeneficial treatment, and the maldistribution of scarce medical resources support physician refusals to honor patient requests for compassionate transfer of embryos, except in the case of impermissible discrimination. Clinics are strongly encouraged to develop and make available written policies regarding patient requests for compassionate transfer of cryopreserved embryos.

Acknowledgments: This report was developed by the Ethics Committee of the American Society for Reproductive Medicine as a service to its members and other practicing clinicians. While this document reflects the views of members of that Committee, it is not intended to be the only approved standard of practice or to dictate an exclusive course of treatment in all cases.

The following members of the ASRM Ethics Committee participated in the development of this document. All Committee members disclosed commercial and financial relationships with manufacturers or distributors of goods or services used to treat patients. Members of the Committee who were found to have conflicts of interest based on the relationships disclosed did not participate in the discussion or development of this document. Judith Daar, J.D.; Jean Benward, M.S.W.; Lee Collins, J.D.; Christos Coutifaris, M.D., Ph.D.; Joseph Davis, D.O.; Owen Davis, M.D.; Leslie Francis, Ph.D., JD; Ruth Farrell, M.D.; Elena Gates, M.D.; Elizabeth Ginsburg, M.D.; Susan Gitlin, Ph.D.; William Hurd, M.D., M.P.H.; Mandy Katz-Jaffe, Ph.D.; Sigal Klipstein, M.D.; Barbara Koenig, Ph.D.; Andrew La Barbera, Ph.D., H.C.L.D.; Laurence McCullough, Ph.D.; Richard Paulson, M.D.; Richard Reindollar, M.D.; Ginny Ryan, M.D.; Mary Samplaski, M.D.; Mark Sauer, M.D., MS; Rebecca Sokol, M.D., M.P.H.; Sean Tipton, M.A.; Lynn Westphal, M.D.; Julianne Zweifel, Ph.D.

REFERENCES

  1. Lyerly AD, Steinhauser K, Voils C, Namey E, Alexander C, Bankowski B, et al. Fertility patients' views about frozen embryo disposition: results of a multi-institutional U.S. survey. Fertil Steril 2010;93:499–509.
  2. Gurmankin AD, Sisti D, Caplan AL. Embryo disposal practices in IVF clinics in the United States. Politics Life Sci 2003;22:4–8.
  3. Nachtigall RD, Becker G, Friese C, Butler A, MacDougall K. Parents' conceptualization of their frozen embryos complicates the disposition decision. Fer til Steril 2005;84:431–4.
  4. Sweet CR, Papkov G, Wiedman-Klayum KC, Norton EL, Miles KF. The number of children living at home and the duration off embryo cryopreservation are significant risk factors for cryopreserved embryos abandonment. Abstract. American Society of Reproductive Medicine (ASRM) Annual Meeting. Salt Lake City: Utah; October 17-19, 2016.
  5. de Lacey S. Parent identity and 'virtual' children: why patients discard rather than donate unused embryos. Hum Reprod 2005;20:1661–9.
  6. Lyerly AD, Steinhauser K, Namey E, Tulsky JA, Cook-Deegan R, Sugarman J, et al. Factors that affect infertility patients' decisions about disposition of frozen embryos. Fertil Steril 2006;85:1623–30.
  7. Merrill JP. Embryos in limbo. The New Atlantis 2009: Spring. Available at: http://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/embryos-in-limbo. Accessed October 3, 2019.
  8. Fertility Smarts Website. Compassionate transfer. Available at: https:// www.fertilitysmarts.com/definition/814/compassionate-transfer. Accessed October 3, 2019.
  9. Lyerly AD, Nakagawa S, Kuppermann M. Decisional conflict and the disposition of frozen embryos: implications for informed consent. Hum Reprod 2011;26:646–54.
  10. Hairston JC, Feinberg EC. Compassionate transfer: provider practices and perspectives. Fertil Steril 2018;110:e374.
  11. Robertson J. Children of choice. New Jersey: Princeton University Press; 1994.
  12. Ethics Committee of the American Society for Reproductive Medicine. Transferring embryos with genetic anomalies detected in preimplantation testing: an Ethics Committee Opinion. Fertil Steril 2017;107:1130–5.
  13. Ethics Committee of the American Society for Reproductive Medicine. Use of reproductive technology for sex selection for nonmedical reasons. Fertil Steril 2015;103:1418–22.
  14. Ethics Committee of the American Society for Reproductive Medicine. Fertility treatment when the prognosis is very poor or futile: an Ethics Committee opinion. Fertil Steril 2019;111:659–63.
  15. Lee K. What happens to the left-overs? Is compassionate transfer ethical? Voices in bioethics. Available at: http://www.voicesinbioethics.net/new swire/2017/2/17/sw388nseb7x0o0e0odngdp5q3m0yg1?rq¼compassiona te%20transfer. Accessed October 3, 2019.

Ethics Opinions

Ethics Committee Reports are drafted by the members of the ASRM Ethics Committee on the tough ethical dilemmas of reproductive medicine.

Use of preimplantation genetic testing for monogenic adult-onset conditions: an Ethics Committee opinion (2024)

Preimplantation genetic testing for monogenic diseases for adult-onset conditions is ethically permissible for various conditions, including when the condition is fully penetrant or confers disease predisposition.
Ethics Committee teaser

Family members as gamete donors or gestational carriers: an Ethics Committee opinion (2024)

The use of adult intrafamilial gamete donors and gestational surrogates is ethically acceptable when all participants are fully informed and counseled.
Ethics Committee teaser

Financial ‘‘risk-sharing’’ or refund programs in assisted reproduction: an Ethics Committee opinion (2023)

Financial ‘‘risk-sharing’’ fee structures in programs charge patients a higher initial fee but provide reduced fees for subsequent cycles.
Ethics Committee teaser

Planned oocyte cryopreservation to preserve future reproductive potential: an Ethics Committee opinion (2023)

Planned oocyte cryopreservation is an ethically permissible procedure that may help individuals avoid future infertility.

More Resources

MAC 2021 teaser
ASRM Academy on the Go

ASRM MAC Tool 2021

The ASRM Müllerian Anomaly Classification 2021 (MAC2021) includes cervical and vaginal anomalies and standardize terminology within an interactive tool format.

View the MAC Tool
EMR Phrases teaser
Practice Guidance

EMR Shared Phrases/Template Library

This resource includes phrases shared by ASRM physician members to provide a template for individuals to create their own EMR phrases.

View the library
Practice Committee Documents teaser

ASRM Practice Documents

These guidelines have been developed by the ASRM Practice Committee to assist physicians with clinical decisions regarding the care of their patients.

View ASRM Practice Documents
Ethics Committee teaser

ASRM Ethics Opinions

Ethics Committee Reports are drafted by the members of the ASRM Ethics Committee on the tough ethical dilemmas of reproductive medicine.

View ASRM Ethics Opinions
Coding Corner general teaser
Practice Guidance

Coding Corner Q & A

The Coding Corner Q & A is a list of previously submitted and answered questions from ASRM members about coding. Answers are available to ASRM Members only.

View the Q & A
Covid-19 teaser
Practice Guidance

COVID-19 Resources

A compendium of ASRM resources concerning the Novel Corona virus (SARS-COV-2) and COVID-19.

View the resources
Couple looking at laptop for online patient education materials

Patient Resources

ReproductiveFacts.org provides a wide range of information related to reproductive health and infertility through patient education fact sheets, infographics, videos, and other resources.

View Website

Topic Resources

View more on the topic of embryo transfer
Coding Icon

How to bill for an FET

Is there a new update to the 89272 code that allows its use without View the Answer
Podcast Icon

Fertility and Sterility On Air - TOC: August 2024

Stay informed with Fertility and Sterility On Air, discussing the latest research on reproductive medicine, obesity, Turner syndrome, and cutting-edge fertility treatments. Listen to the Episode
Coding Icon

Billing Physician vs Service Physician

What physician’s name must be on the treatment notes and who we are permitted to bill to insurance for:   View the Answer
Videos Icon

Journal Club Global: SREI Fellows Retreat - Fellows vs Faculty Debate: Luteal Support in Programmed FET Cycles

Fertility and Sterility Journal Club debate on progesterone administration in frozen embryo transfers, featuring faculty vs fellows discussing IM vs vaginal routes. View the Video
Podcast Icon

Fertility and Sterility On Air - Live from ESHRE 2024: Part 2

Explore fresh embryo transfers, progesterone elevation, and day-seven embryo utility from experts at ESHRE 2024. Cutting-edge fertility insights await! Listen to the Episode
Coding Icon

Who to bill for gestational carrier services if intended parents have insurance?

I wanted to inquire about guidelines for billing services to a surrogate’s insurance company if intended parents purchased the insurance coverage.  View the Answer
Podcast Icon

Fertility and Sterility On Air - TOC: June 2024

Covering articles on embryo transfer, PIEZO-ICSI, pregnancy outcomes, oocyte maturity, estradiol levels, and ovarian carcinoma and more! Listen to the Episode
Podcast Icon

Fertility and Sterility On Air - TOC: May 2024

Topics this month include Iatrogenic and demographic determinants of the national plural birth increase, outcomes between ICSI and IVF with PGT-A. Listen to the Episode
Coding Icon

Coding for an endometrial biopsy/Mock cycle

We had patients request us to bill their insurance for the two monitoring visits and the Endo BX and change the diagnosis code to something that is payable.  View the Answer
PR Bulletin Icon

IVF-assisted pregnancies constitute 2.5% of all births in 2022

In 2022, the number of babies born from IVF increased from 89,208 in 2021 to 91,771 in 2022. This means that 2.5% of births in the US are a result of ART.

View the Press Release
Videos Icon

Journal Club Global - Actualización en la suplementación con progesterona en fase lútea para transferencias de embriones congelados

Efectividad del rescate de progesterona en mujeres que presentan niveles bajos de progesterona circulante alrededor del día de la transferencia de embriones View the Video
Videos Icon

Journal Club Global: Transferencia de embriones frescos versus congelados: ¿Cuál es la mejor opción

Los resultados de nuevas técnicas de investigación clínica que utilizan información de bancos nacionales de vigilancia médica.   View the Video
Coding Icon

CPT 89253 and 89254 for Assisted hatching

Can I bill CPT codes 89253 and 89254 together? If yes, do I need a modifier on any of the codes? View the Answer
Coding Icon

US Embryo Transfer

At the meeting, we learned about the CPT code 76705-Ultasound guidance for embryo transfer, can this code be billed with CPT code 76942? View the Answer
Coding Icon

US Embryo Transfer in Surgery Center

Can we use code 76998 for the ultrasound guidance as this patient is being seen in the Surgery Center? View the Answer
Coding Icon

US Embryo Transfer-Transmyometrial

How would you code for an ultrasound- guided transvaginal-transmyometrial test transfer of embryo catheter? View the Answer
Coding Icon

Uterine Sounding

Is there any specific CPT code(s) for uterine sounding? (Referring to cannulating the cervix and “sounding” or measuring the uterine height)  View the Answer
Coding Icon

Trial Transfer

Can you advise the proper coding process for a trial transfer? View the Answer
Coding Icon

IVF Lab vs Physician Practice Billing

We are planning to open an IVF lab that is not contracted with insurance companies. View the Answer
Coding Icon

In Vitro Maturation

Have CPT codes been established for maturation in vitro? View the Answer
Coding Icon

IVF Case Rates

What ICD-10 codes apply to case rates? View the Answer
Coding Icon

Monitoring FET

What is the correct diagnosis code to use on the follicle ultrasound (76857) for a patient who is undergoing frozen embryo transfer (FET)? View the Answer
Coding Icon

Embryo Thawing/Warming

Is it allowable to bill 89250 for the culture of embryos after thaw for a frozen embryo transfer (FET) cycle? View the Answer
Coding Icon

Endometrial Biopsy/Scratch

What CPT code should be used for a “scratch test”?  View the Answer
Coding Icon

D&C Under Ultrasound Guidance

What are the CPT codes and ICD-10 codes for coding a surgical case for a patient with history of Stage B adenocarcinoma of the cervix ... View the Answer
Coding Icon

Elective Single Embryo Transfer

Has any progress been made in creating/obtaining a specific CPT code for an elective single embryo transfer (eSET)?  View the Answer
Coding Icon

Assisted Hatching Billed With Embryo Biopsy

Do you know if both assisted hatching (89253) and embryo biopsy for PGS/PGD/CCS (89290/89291) can be billed during the same cycle?  View the Answer
Coding Icon

Embryo Transfer

A summary of Embryo Transfer codes collected by the ASRM Coding Committee View the Coding Summary
Videos Icon

Journal Club Global Live from PCRS - Non-Invasive Embryo Selection Techniques

The next great frontier in reproductive medicine is how to non-invasively select an embryo with the highest reproductive potential for transfer. View the Video
Videos Icon

Journal Club Global - Should Fellows Perform Live Embryo Transfers in Fellowship?

Few things are more taboo in reproductive medicine fellowship training than allowing fellows to perform live embryo transfers. View the Video
Videos Icon

Journal Club Global Live from ASRM - Optimal Management of the Frozen Embryo Transfer Cycle: Insights From Recent Literature

Three recent papers published in the Fertility and Sterility family of journals, all explore different aspects of optimizing frozen embryo transfer cycles. View the Video
Document Icon

Compassionate transfer: patient requests for embryo transfer for nonreproductive purposes (2020)

A patient request to transfer embryos into her body in a location or at a time when pregnancy is highly unlikely ... View the Committee Opinion
Document Icon

Blastocyst culture and transfer in clinically assisted reproduction: a committee opinion (2018)

The purposes of this document is to review the literature regarding the clinical application of blastocyst transfer. View the Committee Opinion
Document Icon

Transferring embryos with genetic anomalies detected in preimplantation testing: an Ethics Committee Opinion (2018)

Patient requests for transfer of embryos with genetic anomalies linked to serious health-affecting disorders detected in preimplantation testing are rare but do exist. View the Committee Document
Document Icon

Performing the embryo transfer: a guideline (2017)

A systematic review of the literature was conducted which examined each of the major steps of embryo transfer. Recommendations made for improving pregnancy rates are based on interventions demonstrated to be either beneficial or not beneficial. (Fertil Steril® 2017;107:882–96. ©2017 by American Society for Reproductive Medicine.) View the Committee Guideline
Document Icon

ASRM standard embryo transfer protocol template: a committee opinion (2017)

Standardization improves performance and safety of embryo transfer View the Committee Opinion

Topic Resources

View more on legal/ethical issues
PR Bulletin Icon

ASRM announces support for HOPE with Fertility Services Act

The American Society for Reproductive Medicine is proud to endorse the HOPE with Fertility Services Act (HR 8821).

View the Press Release
Document Icon

Family members as gamete donors or gestational carriers: an Ethics Committee opinion (2024)

The use of adult intrafamilial gamete donors and gestational surrogates is ethically acceptable when all participants are fully informed and counseled. View the Committee Document
Document Icon

Financial ‘‘risk-sharing’’ or refund programs in assisted reproduction: an Ethics Committee opinion (2023)

Financial ‘‘risk-sharing’’ fee structures in programs charge patients a higher initial fee but provide reduced fees for subsequent cycles. View the Committee Document
Document Icon

Planned oocyte cryopreservation to preserve future reproductive potential: an Ethics Committee opinion (2023)

Planned oocyte cryopreservation is an ethically permissible procedure that may help individuals avoid future infertility. View the Committee Opinion
Document Icon

Ethical considerations for telemedical delivery of fertility care: an Ethics Committee opinion (2024)

Telemedicine has the potential to increase access to and decrease the cost of care. View the Committee Opinion
Document Icon

Interests, obligations, and rights in gamete and embryo donation: an Ethics Committee opinion (2019)

This Ethics Committee report outlines the interests, obligations, and rights of all parties involved in gamete and embryo donation: both males and females who choose to provide gametes or embryos for use by others, recipients of donated gametes and embryos, individuals born as a result of gamete or embryo donation, and the programs that provide donated gametes and embryos to patients. View the Committee Opinion
Document Icon

Provision of fertility services for women at increased risk of complications during fertility treatment or pregnancy: an Ethics Committee opinion (2022)

Providers may conclude that the medical risks of fertility treatment for a given patient are too high, in which case it is ethical for them to decline to provide treatment. View the Committee Opinion
Document Icon

Access to fertility services by transgender and nonbinary persons: an Ethics Committee opinion (2021)

The provision of fertility services to transgender individuals and the denial of access to fertility services is not justified. View the Committee Opinion
Document Icon

Interpretation of clinical trial results: a committee opinion (2020)

Evidence from clinical trials is fundamental to ethical medical practice. View the Committee Opinion
Document Icon

Ethics in embryo research: a position statement by the ASRM Ethics in Embryo Research Task Force and the ASRM Ethics Committee (2020)

Scientific research using human embryos advances human health and offspring well-being and provides vital insights into the mechanisms for reproduction and disease. Research involving human embryos is ethically acceptable if it is likely to provide significant new knowledge that may benefit human health, well-being of the offspring, or reproduction. View the Committee Opinion
Document Icon

Compassionate transfer: patient requests for embryo transfer for nonreproductive purposes (2020)

A patient request to transfer embryos into her body in a location or at a time when pregnancy is highly unlikely ... View the Committee Opinion
Document Icon

Use of preimplantation genetic testing for monogenic defects (PGT-M) for adult-onset conditions: an Ethics Committee opinion (2018)

Preimplantation genetic testing for monogenic diseases for adult-onset conditions is ethically permissible for a range of conditions including when the condition is serious and no safe, effective interventions are available. View the Committee Document
Document Icon

Child-rearing ability and the provision of fertility services: an Ethics Committee opinion (2017)

Fertility programs may withhold services on the basis that patients will be unable to provide minimally adequate or safe care for offspring. View the Committee Opinion
Document Icon

Disclosure of medical errors involving gametes and embryos: an Ethics Committee opinion (2016)

Medical providers have an ethical duty to disclose clinically significant errors involving gametes and embryos as soon as they are discovered. Clinics also should have written policies in place for reducing and disclosing errors. View the Committee Document
Document Icon

Informed consent and the use of gametes and embryos for research: a committee opinion (2014)

The ethical conduct of human gamete and embryo research depends upon conscientious application of principles of informed consent. View the Committee Opinion